"THE PROBLEM OF CONDUCT" : A CRITICISM.
- Tuesday, June 10 2014 @ 10:49 am EDT
- Contributed by: webmaster
- Views: 2,779
A great many thanks to The President and Founder at
The Illimitable Ocean of Inexplicability
for his divination of the following publication. Thanks also to The Internet Archive for making this text available. It was the fact that this document contained the term "infinitely remote" that it materialized in search results for the same. What follows is a very interesting and fun (if dry) read.
Posted here for posterity: Enjoy!
460 International Journal of Ethics. "THE PROBLEM OF CONDUCT" : A CRITICISM. When a philosopher boasts that he has riddled with con- tradictions the scientific, moral and religious experiences of mankind, one is forced to ask whether he has not after all been firing at dummies. The principle of contradiction is doubtless a valiant weapon; but sometimes "the engineer is hoist with his own petard." Before we believe that science is vitiated by error to an unknown degree, that morality is at root hypo- crisy, and that religion "inevitably contains and rests upon an element of 'make-believe,' " we must be assured that the meta- physician is dealing with human experience and not with fig- ments of his own elaboration. In criticizing Mr. Taylor's book* I propose to ask two ques- tions. I shall inquire how far on the one hand his theory gives an adequate account of experience, and on the other how far it is consistent with itself. If at any time I appear dogmatic I ask indulgence. I have endeavored to attain clearness at all costs. Sitting on the hedge suggests discomfort ; and although a sprinkling of saving clauses appears more modest and is perhaps more judicious, yet it tends to obscure the question at issue. And this would be most undesirable. We cannot af- ford to treat the problem of conduct like the Scottish minister who exhorted his brethren to look certain difficulties in the face and pass on : this question has got to be faced and an- swered. I propose first of all to give a short account of Mr. Taylor's main line of argument. This is the more desirable inasmuch as his essay contains much matter, interesting perhaps and suggestive, but liable, like pianos and kitchen-ranges in a mobile column, to distract attention and encumber movement. After some general remarks on the nature of metaphysical truth and scientific explanation, Mr. Taylor proceeds to attack the school of moral philosophy associated with the name of T. H. Green. His aim is to expose the fundamental fallacy in every system of ethics, which regards it as a teleological sci- ence in distinction from an empirical investigation. He as- sails Green's contention that a theory of morals should be pre- ceded by a metaphysical analysis of the nature of the self, maintaining that the psychologist is competent to deal with all the facts of morality. Finally he holds that the notion of an eternal self-conscious principle is absurd, and could in no case be of any value for the solution of the problem of con- duct. The ground being so far cleared, the roots of Ethics are •discovered in the moral sentiments of mankind. Theories about motives and obligation, conscience and freedom are rank with popular confusions and fallacious metaphysics. In the words of Paul Somerset "Right and Wrong are but figments and the shadow of a word; but for all that, there are certain things that I cannot do and there are certain others that I will not stand." It is in the feelings or emotions of approval or disapproval, with which men review past or anticipate future actions, that the moralist must find the foundations of his sci- ence. Beginning here the student of ethics will find his groundwork almost completed. For the sentiments awakened by different kinds of action are already embodied in the judg- ments of the market-place, the pulpit, the club and the statute- book. With these as his base the moralist may proceed to give an historical account of the development of ethical feel- ings and ideas; or else attempt to discover the main principle or principles presupposed in the fluid masses of popular opin- ion, and by their help to construct a consistent moral ideal. After a short survey of the evolution of the conceptions of obligation and responsibility, conscience and moral personality, Mr. Taylor attacks the main problem of his essay.
At the outset he discovers an irreconcilable dualism per- meating moral practice and moral theory alike. For men ap- prove of two principles of conduct that are both ultimate and incompatible with one another, — self-assertion and social ser- vice. Even in the biological world this radical divergence may be traced. The evolution of the species demands at once the instincts of self-preservation and self-sacrifice. There, as 462 International Journal of Ethics. in the moral world, the two principles no doubt do not conflict as a rule; but there are cases where self-devotion is required and no compensation allowed. Many have attempted to bring one of these principles under the other ; but this appears impossible. Altruism will not cover all the facts. For as Shakespeare says, "Self-love is not so vile a sin as self-neglecting." A life devoted to social service appears self-contradictory; and is not wholly approved by the sentiments of mankind. Neglect of aesthetic and intellectual self-culture, abnegation of the joys meted to man by a parsi- monious nature, a life of drudgery for the moral or spiritual benefit of others, does not always excite the admiration which is due to complete virtue; and on what ground of reason can we claim that we ought to secure for others what we do not think worth securing for ourselves? Nor can egoism assume the sole title to the throne. Consistent pursuit of personal sat- isfaction, sincere cultivation of science or art, thorough devo- tion to full and harmonious self-development, must involve a man in actions towards others which would call forth the in- dignation of society, if not the severity of the law. Neither egoism nor altruism meet with the full approval of mankind ; and yet there is no recognized principle upon which decisions can be based when these conflict. A compromise is necessary : for no man can succeed in serving with equal devo- tion two masters, himself and his fellows. We are only pre- vented by the arbitrary dictates of established usage from "oscillating perpetually between the two equally ultimate and quite irreconcilable poles" of self-assertion and self-surrender. This radical flaw in morality becomes clearer, if we ask the question, whether either type of moral ideal can be pursued without some departure from that singleness of purpose which is inherent in the nature of every true ideal. The answer may be best summed up in the words of the author : "If your object is self-culture, you have to choose between self-mutilation in one direction for the sake of development in another, and mere superficial dilettanteism, and neither really answers to your original ideal. If your object is social amelioration you can only procure it at the expense of inflicting the very wounds, "The Problem of Conduct;" A Criticism. 463 which you regard it as your mission to heal" (p. 278). For "herein lies the truly laughable paradox of benevolence; ben- evolence has its spring in our pity for the unfit and incapaci- tated, yet the moment you organize it on such lines as to pre- vent it becoming a social pest, it stands revealed as a potent agent in the work of their extermination" (p. 2^2). In short there is "a hidden root of insincerity and hypocrisy beneath all morality" (p. 243). This theory is reinforced by a review of moral progress. On metaphysical grounds Mr. Taylor holds that all progress is illusory. However far the human race may appear to go, the advance cannot be real from the point of view of meta- physics; ex nihilo nihil Hi; every change has its sufficient cause in the totality of its conditions; and therefore, if we could "see life steadily and see it whole," we should find that "the complete reality after the change is identical with the com- plete reality before it" (p. 284). Progress in one quarter only implies retrogression in another ; human endeavor with its vic- tories and its failures means no more than that the Absolute is shuffling the cards. These abstract considerations are supported by some reflec- tions upon the price that has to be paid for civilization, and the impossibility of finding any real satisfaction in the moral life. Literary, artistic and scientific culture may be enjoyed by a few; but it must be bought at the price of an industrial organization, which condemns multitudes to joyless toil and many to ever increasing penury and distress. Along with the cruelty and turbulence of our forefathers civilization threatens to rob us of their courage, their self-reliance, their promptitude in action. Yet "the Koran or the sword" is still our war cry. We are really exterminating the peoples whom we are pleased to think we are civilizing, in order to prepare the way for the creation of a race that is to share our ideals. "Sometimes the extermination is effected by Maxim guns, sometimes by the maxims of the missionary and the school-master" (p. 366). After all we believe that might is right. Finally the goal of ethics is beset with an insoluble anti- nomy. If we are not doomed to irremediable failure, the end 464 Internationai Journal of Ethics. must be something that can be won and enjoyed within the limits of the individual's present life. But a moral end must in its very nature be incapable of attainment. An end worth striving for must be "infinite and therefore infinitely remote" (p. 401). And thus we seem to be damned from our cradles to internal contradiction. The moral life is a kingdom divided against itself. If then the practical life is to be saved at all it must be by falling back upon religion. In Mr. Taylor's opinion the es- sence of religious experience consists in a union of feelings of deep humility and extreme exaltation, of humility, as we con- template the infinite distance that separates us from the ideal, of exaltation, when we reflect that we are "as functions of the perfect universe already perfect." Before God the good and the bad are alike guilty. The universe demands for its perfec- tion vessels of dishonor as well as vessels of honor. God is "a consuming fire" and "a night in which all cows are black." But it is our misfortune that we cannot enjoy these elevating conceptions without hypocrisy. We must strive to be good; for, though the wicked man may be in the eyes of religion already perfect, he does not and cannot, alas ! know himself to be so. But goodness, as we have seen, is unattainable ; and efifort is only an illusion. Hence "all religion inevitably contains and rests upon an element of 'make-believe' " (p. 489). Thus it appears that the practical life is throughout "based upon more or less subtly disguised compromise" (p. 488), and is there- fore self-contradictory and absurd ; and it only remains for the metaphysician to transcend both morality and religion, and in the rare atmosphere of ultimate truth to recognize the "final identity of 'God' and 'Devil' " (p. 492). Such is a brief outline of Mr. Taylor's argument, presented largely in his own words, and, when that is not the case, I hope with scrupulous fidelity to his thought. And I think it may be at once said that no one will be allured into acceptance of his conclusions by their attractiveness. A theory which makes non- sense of life could only claim our assent by demonstrating that its presuppositions are inevitable and its reasoning sound. Some may find it possible to live and work even though they fear that "The Problem of Conduct;" A Criticism. 465 there is and must ever be an internecine war between practice and speculation. But not even "the vulgar" share with the metaphysician the happy facility of saying yes and no at the same moment, of endeavoring to write a book on the problem of conduct to prove that problem and endeavor alike are illu- sory, of rejecting human science as false "to an unknown de- gree of error," in favor of a "knowledge about the ultimate constitution of things," which is after all merely "formal." Before we declare that reason is bankrupt, we must make our- selves quite sure that the accounts are stated correctly. And it is the bankruptcy of reason that Mr. Taylor pro- claims. He speaks no doubt as though the metaphysician has access to a sphere of truth closed to the practical and religious man; but his claim is mere words. His contention that there is a radical flaw in the practical life is suicidal. For the dis- tinction between practical and speculative aspects is, as he acknowledges, merely logical (p. 470). Our thoughts are always directed to the attainment of an ideal goal ; our actions are our actions only because they are impregnated with thought. But instead of examining rigorously this funda- mental interconnection of thinking and striving, Mr. Taylor would summarily dispone of conation in a few paragraphs in the middle of his essay; so that, despite his boast that the panoply of psychology renders his argument invulnerable, he appears to have forgotten his breastplate. To consider this question in detail — Mr. Taylor holds that all the phenomena of mental activity or effort, described by the term "conation," are analyzable into elements of cognition and feeling. He says, "If 'conation' is something psychical, it -will be identical with a peculiar combination of kinsesthetic sensations with varying emotional tension; if it is something more than this, it is apparently identical with muscular con- traction, and is thus purely physiological" (p. 172). For an analysis of successful conation reveals the following facts only. The pleasantly or painfully toned anticipation of a certain ex- perience happens to be followed by a series of complex sensa- tions of sight, pressure, contact and the like, the last term issu- ing in the expected experience. "Throughout the series the Vol. XII.— No. 4. 31 466 International Journal of Ethics. emotional tension arising from the conflict between the feeHngs awakened by the anticipation and those awakened by its con- tinuance in the merely 'ideal' form is constantly changing" (p. 171), until at last it becomes zero as the anticipated pleas- ure is actually enjoyed. In a theory which knows only of cognition and feeling the phrase "emotional tension" seems out of place, and therefore challenges our scrutiny. Emotional tension arises, we are told, "from the contrast between the pleasure of the anticipation and the unpleasantness of its non-realization" (p. 173). Now as Mr. Taylor reminds us elsewhere a pleasure or pain that is not felt is a psychological monstrosity (p. 114). Hence he must mean that two ideas are present to consciousness at once, the one attended by pleasure, the other by pain ; and that these two quarrelsome retainers fall to fighting with each other, and thus produce the necessary emotional tension. This of course is outrageous "symbolism," and contradicted by what Mr. Taylor says in another place. "It should never be for- gotten," he says, "that in speaking of the pleasurable or pain- ful character of a particular sensation or idea [in distinction from the whole content of consciousness] we are indulging in exactly the same abstracting process as when we describe an explosion as due to the lighting of the fuse" (p. 121). But if we remember this, and insist that emotional tone never belongs to a single sensation or idea, but to the whole content of con- sciousness only, what are we to make of the "emotional ten- sion" which is so prominent a feature in conative processes? We cannot say that the whole content of consciousness is at one and the same time both pleasantly and painfully toned ; but, as this is impossible, where are we to find the contrast or conflict of pleasure and pain ? This reasoning is no doubt of the nature of an argumentum ad hominem; but wherever an attempt is made to get rid of conation it will be found to return in disguise. If then emo- tional tension is cut out of Mr. Taylor's account, nothing is left save a series of kinsesthetic sensations. But these alone afford no ground for the distinction of reflex from volitional actions. I take snuff in the pleasant expectation of sneezing. The action "The Problem of Conduct;" A Criticism. 467 is followed in due course by the desired effect over which I have no control. I rise to propose a toast anticipating with pleasure the resumption of my seat; but the intervening five minutes are filled with feelings of intense effort. In each case I have expectations succeeded by various sensations; but in the latter the sense of endeavor is great, in the former it is, if it can be said to exist at all, a negligible quantity. And moreover, how can a theory which identifies conation with kinaesthetic sensations deal with the case of a man who is trying to understand a book or work out an idea, as we say, in his head? Nowhere is the sense of effort stronger; but where are the sensations of sight, pressure, contact and the like? And if Mr. Taylor, following certain eminent authori- ties, should assert that here the contraction of the eyebrows, the setting of the teeth, and the like, give the requisite sensa- tions we would ask in return, how it is possible to experience these sensations and yet not try to understand anything at all, and vice versa. But in truth those who extrude conation from psychology remind one of the proverb of not seeing the wood for the trees. In the greater part of our waking life we are pursuing ends, trying to realize ideas, be they far-reaching or trifling, with varying effort and success. As Mr. Taylor insists, all truly human conduct is "telic" or purposive (p. 188), determined by the more or less definite anticipation of an end or result. But does not this imply an active principle "which constitutes self- hood, without which there would be no self and strictly speak- ing no humanity at all ?" Discard activity, attention, endeavor, and you withdraw the rivets without which life would never be other than a chaotic manifold of sensations and feelings. The psychologist must choose one of two courses; either he must recognize activity — the fact that we more or less systematically direct the focus of consciousness, so to speak, to this or that part of the total field, — or else he must admit that ideas some- how hold together "like the bits of stick and sand with which the young caddis covers its nakedness." If he dislikes the latter alternative, he must acknowledge conation. Perhaps the term "conation" is not quite appropriate for the element I wish 468 International Journal of Ethics. to indicate. It suggests effort, which is a special form of ac- tivity, and presupposes a felt obstacle that must be overcome. In the same way the popular use of the term "attention" implies a conscious attempt to fix an idea or bring some part of the content of consciousness more fully into view. But even where there is no sense of effort, where introspection cannot dis- cover anything which may be confused with kinsesthetic sensa- tions, emotional tension and what not, we still seem justified in insisting upon the activity of the mind. In reverie we keep our ideas in the channel that pleases us, we select this aspect and reject that, although we have no such experience of strain as we suffer when we determine to listen to a very dull ser- mon. If it is true that Mozart composed and Scott wrote with- out effort, it is absurd to think of them merely as passive ob- servers of their ideas. Even observation means activity. But Mr. Taylor will have nothing to do with the concept of mental activity. Since he deals with human conduct upon the platform of popular opinion and natural science, he demands that ethics shall use only the categories of physics and chemistry, although he is quite ready upon occasion to employ the higher conceptions of teleology. Such confusion seems inevitable if on^ determines to base morals upon the un- criticized sentiments of mankind, without any preliminary in- vestigation, whether called metaphysical or not, into the point of view ironi which ethical conduct ought to be regarded. Mr. Taylor regards the ideas of activity and free cause as worthless. For, he tells us, science requires a concept of causal relation which can be applied indiscriminately to the changes in the organic and the inorganic world. The organic world apparently includes both the physiological and psychological aspects of life. Otherwise why should ethics not employ such a concept as that of a free cause ? But it is difficult to gratify the desire for a conception of causality that shall be equally ap- plicable to physical and psychical changes. For however closely cerebral and mental processes are intertwined, it must be admitted that there is no such continuity between them as is found in physical and chemical changes. There is no common element. In the former the amount of energy — ^actual or po- "The Problem of Conduct,-" A Criticism. 469 tential — remains constant; in the latter the atomic weights remain the same. But where is the identical element in the idea of lighting my pipe and the nervous and muscular move- ments necessary to its realization? A natural science may believe that it has found a true cause when it has discovered the definite conditions under which a given change will regularly occur, and without which it will not take place. Natural philosophy has no doubt made great advances because it has concentrated its attention upon the discovery of "unconditional antecedents," without troubling about the perhaps insoluble question, how physical changes do occur. But until physicists have made a real conquest over psychical life, instead of blus- tering about it in inappropriate metaphors drawn from physics, electricity or chemistry, they have no right to command psychologists, as Mr. Taylor does, to substitute for "force" some such phrase as "rate of change of momentum" (p. 20), or denote by energy only what "can be calculated in terms of mass and velocity." Those who hold that we have no direct experience of activity should attempt to explain how it is that children and savages inform all objects with it, and only learn by long experience that things are not persons. Activity, force, energy are so far from being the merely symbolic ex- pressions of "spiritualist philosophers" and scientific obscurant- ists that they are among the most elementary facts of the expe- rience of a child. Having rejected activity, Mr. Taylor naturally relapses from time to time into psychological atomism. On the one hand, it is true, he recognizes Hume's failure to destroy personal identity, and holds that "the self," to which the contents of all my adult experiences, in so far as they are attended to at all, are related as "its" experiences, cannot possibly be identified with any one in the series of experiences, nor yet with the mere succession considered simply as a succession of atomic psych- ical events" (p. 71). But on the other hand, when discussing the nature of the self, he says, "in the empirically ascertained fact that the organic sensations and the accompanying feeling- tone are relatively stable within long periods of life, we have all that is necessary for the growth of a distinction between 470 International Journal of Ethics. the permanent self and its incessantly changing sensations and ideas" (p. 73). I freely admit that relatively stable organic sensations and generally speaking a relatively stable environ- ment are essential to personal identity, so far as we know it. In wonderland Alice might well exclaim "Who in the world am I?" But are relatively permanent organic sensations all that is necessary? To what are they relatively permanent? To the self? But the self is their product. Surely here the admitted absurdity is committed of identifying the self with certain of its experiences. The self is reduced to an aggregate of sensations which have been strong enough to force them- selves into the forefront of consciousness. For as Mr. Taylor says, "Attending to a presentation seems to be no more than another name for the fact that that presentation is successful in detaching itself from the larger mass of undifferentiated consciousness" (p. 11). A fictitious self receives within its fictitious embrace those presentations which jostle most vigor- ously against it. This is indeed psychological atomism, which, however serviceable, is admitted to be "inadequate to the point of absurdity" (p. 85). We may now take leave of Mr. Taylor's psychology and turn to his metaphysics. He holds that it is a "radically mis- chievous" error to regard progress as real. On the contrary "All progress is an illusion — a phenomenon which disappears the moment you cease to concentrate your attention on some one subordinate part of the whole world of facts to the neglect of all the rest" (p. 281). What from our point of view is sheer loss and retrogression would, if our outlook upon the world were from a different quarter, appear as pure gain and progress. "In the universe as a whole there is neither gain nor loss but simply compensation" (p. 283). I should like in passing to protest against this notion of com- pensation. It may be applicable to changes in a material sys- tem, and to whatever can be adequately translated into terms of money, but to say that the extinction of a human soul can be balanced in the account of the universe seems to me nonsense. If a life rich in experience and character is snuflfed out, that is sheer loss; a loss in no sense made good by the transference "The Problem of Conduct;" A Criticism. 471 of the germ of life to some distant constellation whether on the meteoric fragments of an exploded planet or otherwise {of. p. 283). But ultimately compensation, according to Mr. Taylor's argument, is unintelligible. For it means change and change even within the universe is mere appearance. There may be a redistribution of energy within a partial system, while the total energy of the system and its relation to other systems remains the same {cf. p. 314). For from the wider point of view the partial system is seen to maintain its identity through its changes. But how is it possible "to find a point of view from which a whole, standing in no relations to anything outside it- self, can be seen to be the same whole though it appears now as A now as B" (p. 314) ? The problem is insoluble. Either the identity or the changes must be sacrificed. Either we must say "there is not really a whole at all, but only disconnected and utterly disparate successive states, which are states of noth- ing" (p. 314) ; or we must conclude that "change and becom- ing" would vanish altogether, if once we could take in the whole contents of reality in a single comprehensive experience (p-315)- Mr. Taylor accepts* the latter alternative and draws the fit- ting corollary that the universe is already perfect; that en- deavor is a delusion; right and wrong are but figments and the shadow of a word; ignorance no less than knowledge, misery no less than happiness, crime, lust, murder no less than courage, purity, justice are necessary to the unspeakable bless- edness and perfection of the Absolute. Perhaps only "the vulgar" would accept this inference as a sufficient refutation of a metaphysical theory. I must therefore endeavor to examine it on its own ground, although it would be presumptions to hope to do more than ofifer a few well-worn suggestions upon so important and well recognized a crux as change. First then we may note that however absurd it may seem to speak of identity in difference, to say that one and the same thing passes through successive phases, it is the one kind of experience that is always with us. We change ; our environ- ment changes ; yet we cannot say with Heracleitus xdvra fiet 472 International Journal of Ethics. ebSiv ixivet. We abide. Otherwise how could we possibly experience any series of events? Further it seems absurd to attempt to extract the identity or the differences from the whole and isolate either of them. For a bare identity would be nothing. And differences that were not differences of something, that, however disparate in them- selves, were not at least united by their presence to one con- sciousness, would not be differences at all. Yet certain critics offer us a dilemma based upon the assumption that reason should be able to segregate these mutually dependent elements. They challenge us either to separate the one self from its many appearances, as though they were chemical elements, and pro- duce them bottled, sealed and labelled; or else to admit that personal identity is a fiction practically convenient perhaps but intellectually ridiculous. In regard to progress, Mr. Taylor holds that either the iden- tity of the whole or its changes must be sacrificed ; and which- ever operation is chosen, progress is doomed. I cannot see that we are bound to grasp at either horn of the dilemma. It is as true, or false, to say that identity is an accidental aspect of change, as that change is an accidental aspect of identity. Both are necessary. No doubt science demands that the com- plete reality after the change shall be identical with the com- plete reality before it. But science also demands a process. Causal explanation would be meaningless if antecedent and consequent were telescoped into one timeless existence. Evo- lution in the same way compels us to adopt both points of view. The embryo is in one sense the full grown animal ; in another sense it is not. Or what would be the meaning of the growth ? But perhaps it will be said ; "Human experience does indeed presuppose identity in difference, the permanent in change ; but that fact does not make it a whit more rational ; on the contrary it demonstrates its unintelligibility." Now I do not contend that human thought has found adequate expression for the fullness of its experience. We are compelled to shift our ground continually in order to view this or that aspect ; so far are we from being able to see life steadily and see it whole. But I do hold that it is unphilosophical, first to call one aspect "The Problem of Conduct f A Criticism. 473 reality, and another mere appearance; and secondly to talk of human experience as vitiated to the core by self-contradic- tory principles in contrast to the pure experience of the Abso- lute. Such a philosophy is the counterpart of that mysticism which is so absorbed in the beauty and holiness of the unseen and eternal as to regard this world as altogether hideous and vile. For, if human experience is so radically afHicted with discord, hypocrisy and vanity, as Mr. Taylor would lead us to suppose, what meaning is conveyed by the phrase "pure ex- perience of the Absolute?" To say that it is harmonious and comprehensive conveys to me at least nothing. To say that it is eternally the same suggests to me only boredom. In a word if we may not assume that the constitution of the human mind is on the whole truthful and trustworthy, we may as well give up philosophy as but an idle amusement not worth the trouble. If those conceptions that make experience possible are vicious through and through, it is nonsense for men to claim that they possess a science of metaphysics which can throw light upon the ultimate constitution of things. So far I have endeavored to cut the ground away from Mr, Taylor's feet by indicating what appear to me as radical defects in his psychological and metaphysical presuppositions. I shall now attempt to exhibit the fallacy in his argument that morality is vitiated by an irreconcilable dualism. He contends that there are two ultimate moral principles, egoism and altruism, neither of which alone comprehends all the facts, while no higher cate- gory can be found to adjust their rival claims. The one prin- ciple says "Enrich yourself at all costs; find out and satisfy your inclinations; discover your powers and cultivate them resolutely though the heavens threaten ruin." The other re- plies "Spend yourself in the service of others; do what you most dislike; deny all if only you may make others happier." "Build for thy soul a lordly pleasure house" sings the one; and the other answers harshly "Live laborious days." Such are the twin principles of morality, implicit obedience to either of which would render life intolerable if not impossible. Com- promise is therefore necessary; and compromise is only a fair name for hypocrisy. Few will deny that if egoism and altru- 474 International Journal of Ethics. ism, as just presented, are ultimate ethical principles, then morality is distracted by an irresoluble contradiction. Altru- ism is absurd; for it bids us trample on that pearl of great price which we are morally bound to save for others. Egoism is absurd; for it bids us fill with a sieve a broken pitcher. And no sane man could hope to effect a compromise. But are ego- ism and altruism ultimate moral principles? Had Mr. Taylor confined his illustrations and arguments to proving this, his demonstration of the bankruptcy of morality would hardly have appeared plausible. But he has confused the self-assertion of Thrasymachus or Callicles with the Hege- lian idea of self-realization, and the self-sacrifice or altruism of popular text-books with the Platonic conception of social justice. A careful reader of "The Problem of Conduct" will I think find this accusation fair. Apart from such phrases as "The Hegelian egoists of the school of Green" (p. 224), self- realization is constantly used as equivalent to self-culture, self- assertion and egoism, and justice is made a variant for social service, self-sacrifice and altruism. "The highest and most perfect expression of the principle of moral altruism" says Mr. Taylor, "seems to be found in that law of justice," according to which the duties erf each individual are determined by the common good of all (p. 202). But how can this principle be fairly identified with altruism, unless altruism is regarded as a principle, which attempts to decide as to the relative claims of self and others, and does not arbitrarily make over every- thing to the latter? But if this view is accepted, Mr. Taylor's refutation of altruism falls to the ground. But perhaps the Platonic ideal of justice is as absurd as altruism in the stricter sense of the word. This is Mr. Taylor's view. For, as he says, the demands of the common good "may prevent a man from doing full justice to his own powers and capabilities of intellectual or physical development" (p. 204) ; he may be compelled "to mutilate himself" for the sake of his family or his country ; the state may hinder him from purchas- ing the satisfaction of his tastes and passions with the sweat and blood of his fellow-men. Doubtless this is a serious difficulty, if egoism is to be accepted as an ultimate moral principle. But why "The Problem of Conduct;" A Criticism. 475 should one make this assumption? Why should one accept egoism as the ultimate principle of morality? Who is the egoist? Is he the man, whose archetype is the dog in the manger ; one who snarls and grumbles over what is worthless ; who cultivates himself, yet grows not; a dilettante in art and literature, a man of the world ? Shuddering at the thought of arrested development and self-mutilation, he sneers at the hypocrisy of the vulgar in catchwords borrowed from a philos- ophy he has never taken the pains to understand. Can this man be one of our moral ideals? We appeal to Mr. Taylor's jury, the moral sentiments. The case goes against him by default. This egoist dare not challenge the popular verdict. But perhaps this species is too tame. The true egoist is one who has many and great lusts and is determined to satisfy them. He desecrates love and beauty, then tosses them aside; his meat and drink are robbery, rape and murder. Have we found our ideal? The jury need hardly be asked to consider their verdict. But, I shall be told, these sketches are unfair. Mr. Taylor does not mean by egoist either of these monsters. It may be so ; for he does not make his position clear. Many of his illus- trations point to one or other of these t)^s; and I confess 1 cannot see any other issue, if the cleavage between the self and others is logically maintained. If a man considers every act with his eye concentrated upon his own private satisfaction, regardless of the claims of others, his family, his neighbors and his country ; if he rejects all ideals the realization of which will transcend his own finite experience, then his life will ap- proximate to one or other of the extremes that I have indi- cated, the direction being determined partly by the vehemence of his passions, partly by the opportunities of his environment. But Mr. Taylor is too adroit to leave egoism in this sorry plight ; he summons the theory of self-realization to aid. The strenuous pursuit of an ideal of art or knowledge is introduced as an aspect of egoism. But how can the chasm between the self and others now be kept open? If a man is sincere in the desire that a certain ideal should be realized, is it essential that he should privately enjoy the satisfaction of its realization? 476 International Journal of Ethics. Will he not lay down even his life for it? Must he not in any case suppress many sides of his nature, leave idle many capaci- ties, "mutilate" himself, if he would seek the pearl of great price? As Mr. Taylor has shown, his type of egoism, the scholar, is in many respects the type of self-sacrifice. He sac- rifices money, position, health ; deserts many an enchanting isle if only he may get a glimpse of the truth; and how often when evening comes he is found but as a little child gathering shells upon the sea-shore. Thus the fundamental contradiction of morality seems to vanish. Altruism is absorbed in social justice; egoism is taken up into self-realization. And these do not conflict. For Plato's theory of social justice is only the theory of self- real- ization, presented in a form such as was suitable when the conception of the city-state seemed to represent the richest, most harmonious and comprehensive type of society possible. In the realization of the common good each individual attains his highest development and fullest satisfaction. But, I shall be told, even if it is inaccurate to describe mo- rality as a thinly disguised hypocrisy, yet satisfaction can never be expected from it, since the moral ideal must be "infinite and therefore infinitely remote" (p. 401). However we strive, we are not a jot nearer our goal at the last than at the first; whatever we do, we "fall equally short of the 'heart's desire' " (p. 395). But is an ideal that is "infinite therefore infinitely remote?" Is there not here an equivocation in the use of "in- finite?" We say the moral ideal must be infinite, meaning that it must be complete, perfectly satisfying, conditioned by noth- ing beyond. But when we speak of space as infinite, we mean that it can not limit itself. The phrase "infinite distance" is really unintelligible, since it implies an extensive quantity at once definite and indefinite. One might as well talk of invis- ible colors or inaudible sounds. It does not therefore seem to follow that an infinite ideal must be infinitely remote. And an appeal to experience surely shows that Mr. Taylor's assertion IS unfounded. Complete satisfaction in any sphere of human life is doubtless out of the question. Conditioned as we are by a physical organism which grows and decays in the world Scholars of the Cloister — A Defence. 477 of time and space we cannot hope to exhaust the fullness of the world. But there is a difference between complete satisfac- tion and no satisfaction at all. If the ideal is never actualized here, yet it need not altogether elude us. So long as he has strength, the plain man is content to go on working as well as he can. Something is accomplished ; and he is not unhappy. Why be like an unwholesome schoolboy who is always count- ing the number of hours until the holidays, and never enjoys them when they come? But time forbids me to pursue these reflections any further. I trust that my arguments have not "been unfair. But a book which makes nonsense of life must expect unveiled hostility. We do not want a philosophy "which finds bad reasons for being what we cannot help being" (p. 201), and then spurns human experience, permitting, if anything, what seem the deepest and truest views of life to be retained merely on scientific sufferance. We want an idealism which, having reached some peak of speculation, can tell us the true relations of what we from the valleys see fitfully amid the storm and the mist. But for the true philosopher, as for the poet and the artist, we must await the favor of heaven. In the meantime, however, there is employment for the humble spade- worker. He may. prepare the ground for the new seed, hy trenching diligently and trying to subvert the luxuriant aftermath of the last philosophical harvest. Alfred J. Jenkinson. Hertford College, Oxford. SCHOLARS OF THE CLOISTER: A DEFENCE. It is one of the commonplaces of history that spiritual or ecclesiastical Rome did not fall with material, political Rome. The Roman Church was a product at once of Latin and of Christian influences, being in its splendid organization a special tribute to the Roman Law and in its peculiar power a witness to the vitality which the spirit of Christianity gave to the Law, and in consequence it was able to withstand the barbarian